I've spent the last month or so writing entries on Hölderlin, Hegel, and Schelling for The Jean-Luc Nancy Dictionary. This task has forced me to summarize the life and work of Schelling, for instance, in something like 500-600 words. That's no easy task. Here is my work in progress.
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph
Schelling (1775–1854) is a German philosopher who made important—though now
often-neglected—contributions to the metaphysics of German idealism, philosophy
of nature, philosophy of art, and theology. His work is typically divided into
various periods (cf. Dunham et al).
During the first, which culminates in his System of Transcendental
Idealism (1800), Schelling undertakes a
critique of post-Kantian transcendental idealism, in which he develops a
nature-philosophy and a philosophy of art. Nature-philosophy aims to
demonstrate: first, the natural basis of the subject’s activity, and second, an
organic concept of nature that emphasizes the centrality of nature’s
productivity (the Spinozist natura naturans) and the processes of chemistry, electricity, and
magnetism, rather than reducing natural processes to a merely mechanistic
physics. The philosophy of art, which Schelling called the “keystone” of this
system, has three characteristics. Artistic production, or what he calls
“aesthetic intuition,” demonstrates the unity of unconscious (natural) and
conscious production; it realizes concretely (in the real) what philosophy
demonstrates ideally (in contrast to practical reason, which can only
approximate its object, the categorical imperative); and it opens the
possibility of producing a new mythology which can unite a people in an organic
community.
In 1801, Schelling announces “his” system of philosophy, a bold
return to metaphysics in the aftermath of the Kantian critical project, that he
calls identity-philosophy or absolute idealism. While nature-philosophy and the philosophy of art play
prominent roles in this period, Schelling advances (in collaboration with
Hegel) a critique of the subjective idealism of Kant and Fichte. Rather than
positing the practical subject or absolute I as the foundation of the system,
he argues that philosophy must proceed from the identity of subject and object.
This identity is necessary, he claims, to explain the correspondence of the
knower and what is known—subject and object—rather than presupposing it.
The
third period includes Schelling’s Philosophical Investigations into
the Essence of Human Freedom (1809) and the
various drafts of the Weltalter (Ages
of the World). During this period,
Schelling turns against, and critiques, the presuppositions of
identity-philosophy—in short, the idea that logical necessity qua reason is the
basis of all intelligibility. His philosophy of freedom explores the natural
and historical-theological conditions necessary for human freedom, which is conceptualized as an existential decision rather than modeled
on the categorical imperative.
The final period of Schelling’s work, which is
characterized as the philosophy of revelation, takes shape around 1830 and
remains a central preoccupation until his death. Though this work was only
published posthumously, he delivered parts of it at the University of Berlin
when he assumed in 1841 what was once Hegel’s chair in philosophy. Schelling
aims to integrate critical or negative philosophy with what he called positive
philosophy. Negative philosophy (which is associated, in modern terms, with
post-Kantian philosophy) serves to eliminate what is contingent from the “first
concepts of being”—it is confined to the essence or whatness of beings (2007:
144). Positive philosophy thinks the thatness or the fact of existence of God
using the historical-theological resources of Greek mythology and Christian
revelation.
On the basis of the differences between these periods, many
commentators have concluded that Schelling was a protean thinker who never
brought a system to conclusion. This
conclusion overlooks his continued attention to the relationship—despite the
changing significances of the terms—between “freedom” and “system.” For
Schelling, free activity precludes and prevents the possibility of a completed
system. In his Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism (1795-1796), for instance, he argues that a complete
system cannot be lived by a philosopher: at that “moment [its creator] would
cease to be creator and would be
degraded to an instrument” of his or her system (1980: 172).
Works Cited
Dunham, Jeremy, Iain Hamilton Grant and Sean Watson. Idealism: The History of a Philosophy (Durham: Acumen, 2011).
Schelling, F.W.J. (1980). “Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and
Criticism,” in The Unconditional in Human Knowledge. Trans. Fritz Marti (Lewisburg: Bucknell University
Press, 1980), 156–218.
–––– (2007). The Grounding of
Positive Philosophy. Trans. Bruce Matthews
(Albany: SUNY Press).
No comments:
Post a Comment